I defend a reasons-responsive theory of free will. As a compatibilist, I am committed to showing
that an adequate account of such freedom can be advanced without at any point
requiring the falsity of determinism. Roughly,
reasons-responsive theories account for free will in terms of an agent’s responsiveness
to an adequate spectrum of reasons. In
my estimation, reasons-responsive theories have several advantages over what
are known as mesh theories, theories that are also often offered in the service
of defending compatibilism. Again, speaking
only roughly, mesh theories account for free will in terms of a harmoniously
functioning mesh of psychic subsystems collectively generating action.
As I see it, one striking advantage of reasons-responsive theories over
mesh theories, such as Harry Frankfurt’s, is that the former are not plagued by
a difficulty that seems endemic to the latter.
The problem is just that mesh theorists characterize acting freely in
terms of action flowing from a harmonious mesh.
On Frankfurt’s view, for instance, it is when one’s will (one’s
effective first-order desire) is aligned with what, at a higher-order of
desires, one, by way of identification, wants one’s will to be. The mesh here is a meshing of higher-order
desires working in harmony with lower-order desires. The problem, however, for views with a mesh structure
is that they seem handicapped in their ability to distinguish between acting
unfreely because of acting from an unharmonious mesh as opposed to freely
acting from an unharmonious mesh. To use
a case of Frankfurt’s as an example, recall the unwilling addict, who does not
act freely and is not responsible, and now consider instead a weak-willed
non-addict, who freely takes the drug and is responsible for doing so despite
instead judging it best that she not take the drug, and despite identifying
with her desire not to do so. Frankfurt,
it seems, cannot readily explain the difference between these agents. The problem is not unique to Frankfurt’s mesh
theory, so far as I can tell. Other mesh
theorists like Gary Watson and Michael Bratman also face a similar problem. (For my money, Bratman has the most promising
mesh theory, but that is the subject for another post.)
The reason that I describe the above problem for mesh theorists as a
striking advantage for reasons-responsive theorists is because, where mesh
theorists have a hard time accounting for these sorts of problems, for
reasons-responsive theorists, this is a cake walk: The weak-willed non addict
is responsive to a richer spectrum of reasons for not taking the drug, and takes
it from causal sources that are suitably sensitive to that richer spectrum of
reasons. The unwilling adduct is not
responsive to as rich a spectrum of reasons and takes the drug from causal
sources that are not suitably sensitive to that spectrum.
Not long ago, John Martin Fischer posted on our Flickers site and
developed this criticism for mesh theories.
Now it might well be that mesh theorists can overcome this criticism,
and showing why I think they cannot requires far more space than I have
available here. But what I am interested
in at present is, so to speak, the flip side of this criticism. Mesh theorists might put to
reasons-responsive theorists the criticism that there is a lacuna in their reasons-responsive
accounts, a serious short-coming that ought to force them to take on at least some
of the features of a mesh theory so as to avoid the charge that they simply
fail to capture an important dimension of free and responsible agency. The lacuna in their account, the mesh
theorists might argue, is precisely that reasons-responsive theories do nothing
to capture the internal features of our agency, and that this is not merely one
further element that ought to be explained among others in a theory of freedom,
but concerns the most fundamental features of our nature as (free) persons.
To develop this criticism of reasons-responsive theories, consider
again Frankfurt’s famous 1971 paper “Freedom and the Will and the Concept of a
Person.” On his view, only a person is
able to adopt attitudes about her own motivational states as they bear upon her
agency in the world. Being so structured,
only a person, Frankfurt essayed, is in a position to face a certain problem
about her own will in that it might not be as she herself wants it to be. Now Frankfurt executed this view in a
particular way (by, among other things, reference to an ability to form
volitions). And I have ignored these
details here. I am more interested in
the general structural features of mesh theories that seem to me to get at
something quite deep about our agency as free persons. We could instead theorize, as Watson does, in
terms of the relation between one’s motivational and her evaluative systems and
the way that a person might adopt certain evaluative attitudes towards the “forces”
moving her to action. Alternatively, ala
Bratman, we might do this by way of higher-order planning policies that structure
for us our commitments and guide our preferences but yet can be foiled by
haywire forces that gum up he works and lead to defects of agency.
In general, I believe that these mesh theories capture something right,
something deep and important about our free agency as persons and candidates
for moral responsibility. And from what
I can tell, we reasons-responsive theorists have just not built into our
theories features of agency that pay adequate attention to the internal psychic
structures that give rise to these problems.
Mesh theorists might quip back, then, at the likes of Fischer, Haji, me
and numerous other reasons-responsive theorists (I would include in our camp
Dana Nelkin, David Brink, Carolina Sartorio, Michael Smith, Kadri Vihvelin,
Susan Wolf, and numerous others), that with no more than the resources of
responsiveness to reasons, we cannot showcase the special place of the unique
internal structure of a person’s will (as Frankfurt would put it), since all we
have are sets of reasons to which an agent must be responsive. Of course, reasons-responsive theorists could
simply contend that the spectrum of reasons to which a free agent must be
responsive must include reasons she has presented by her own internal
psychology. (This is how I have always
imagined that I could solve this problem.)
But in fairness to the mesh theorists, this just seems inadequate. My relation to my own internal states and the
problems of agency posed by my complex nature as a person is not like my
relation to the reasons afforded to me by the world as I find it. I have some ideas here, but I’ll not show my
hand, at least not now. I’m curious as
to what all of you think.
Oh, one more thing: I’d like to plug this as a problem for anyone who
wants to advance a positive account of free will, which includes
libertarianism. Why? You libertarians out there should also be
interested in the nature of freedom, aside from the compatibility issue. It is open to you, as Carl Ginet has proposed
in assessing Fischer and Ravizza’s view, to embrace the best compatibilist proposal
of freedom and then just tack on a requirement of indeterminism (suitably
located, of course).
Sorry for the long post. It took
a bit of effort to lay this one out. Hope
you find it interesting!
Recent Comments